Empiricism holds that our
knowledge of the world comes primarily from experience, and
rationalism that it comes primarily from reason. An extreme
rationalist would believe that we are born with knowledge of all
the universal forms tucked away in our minds, and that we only come
to know the world in the light of this knowledge. An extreme
empiricist, on the other hand, would believe that our minds contain
nothing at birth and only acquire knowledge by seeing and
experiencing the world. When applied to aesthetics, rationalism
tends towards the view that art should represent the world of the
forms, and empiricism to the the view that it should represent the
world of experience. Rationalist art makes great use of regularity,
proportion and mathematics, while empiricist art delights in
wildness, irregularity and unexpected details. The two conceptions
of art depend on two views of how man comes to know the 'nature' of
the world.
Return to section
heading
John
Locke was the most important empiricist philosopher to
influence the course of eighteenth century garden design but he was
not an extreme empiricist: elements of both views are to be found
in his writings. He is however more empiricist than any British
philosopher who preceded him. It would be fascinating to learn more
of Locke's views on gardening. We know that he advised his patron
on 'the layout of his gardens' but it was probably on technical
matters. His little book on gardening contains nothing on
aesthetics but a good deal of information about the cultivation of
the vine. Locke's influence on garden design came about through his
patron, the First Earl of
Shaftesbury, and through his pupil, the Third Earl of Shaftesbury.
Return to
section heading
The third Earl of Shaftesbury was a
firm supporter of the Neoplatonic theory of art. He believed that
the artist should represent the simplest and purest forms. 'Why',
Shaftesbury asks, 'is the sphere or globe, the cylinder and obilisk
preferred; and the irregular figures in respect of these, rejected
and despised?'. His answer to the question is thoroughly
Neoplatonic. Simple and pure shapes are preferred because 'the
beautiful, the fair, the comely were never in the matter.....but in
the form or forming power'. It is clear that Shaftesbury has
assigned each of the geometrical shapes a hierarchical position.
The sphere and cylinder occupy high positions and the irregular
figures lowly positions. Neoplatonists have often interpreted
Plato in this manner, but though he
does refer to the sphere as 'the most perfect and most like itself
of all the figures', Plato himself was uninterested in the
positions of the other shapes.
It is also notable that Shaftesbury, like Pope, uses the word
'nature' in several different senses. In the following passage he
uses 'unnatural' to describe the painter who 'strictly copies
life', but 'nature' to describe the scene which he copies: A
painter, if he has any genius, understands the truth and unity of
design; and knows he is even unnatural when he copies nature too
close, and strictly copies life.
The injunction not to copy life too strictly appears to conflict
with Shaftesbury's oft-quoted remark that 'I shall no longer resist
the passion growing in me for things of natural kind'. The apparent
conflict is explained by the presence of a strong current of
empiricism running through Shaftesbury's essentially rationalist
philosophy. Like Plato, he believed that our knowledge of the forms
can be increased by a study of the particulars which compose the
visible world. A visual symbol of this truth could be provided by a
Palladian villa, based on the circle and square, set in a wild and
irregular landscape. Had Shaftesbury lived for another twelve years
(ie until 1725) he could have seen beautiful illustrations of this
idea at Mereworth Castle in Kent
(designed by Colen Campbell) and at
Chiswick House (designed by Lord Burlington and William Kent). Both are closely based on Andrea
Palladio's design of 1552 for the Villa Capra at Vicenza. The small
Palladian temples which were
later used to adorn Stourhead and
many other English landscape gardens also illustrate Shaftesbury's
point.
|
Andrea Palladio's Villa
Capra, near Vicenza. The design was based on the principle of
harmonic proportion, incorporating the circle and the square. The
imitation of these 'forms' in architecture was a method by which
buildings were enabled to partake of the 'nature' of the
world. |
Return to
section heading
In the middle years of the
eighteenth century, when Stourhead was being laid out and Lancelot Brown held the post of Royal
Gardener at Hampton Court, there was a
balance in the minds of garden designers between the regular and
irregular conceptions of nature. By the end of the century the
irregular conception had scored a complete victory.
William Gilpin's partisan enthusiasm for the rough and rugged
aspects of nature turned the Neoplatonic theory of art completely
upside down. There is no clearer illustration of what happened than
in the writings of William Gilpin's nephew, a nineteenth century
landscape gardener with the name William
Sawry Gilpin.
Return to section
heading
Sawry Gilpin published a book in 1832 with the title
Practical Hints upon Landscape Gardening. In it he expresses
his confusion and total exasperation over a footnote in the first
edition of Sir Henry Steuart's
Planter's Guide. Steuart had suggested that if anyone was
not so fortunate as to have the use of a Lancelot Brown tree
transplanter to produce instant irregularity then, as a temporary
expedient, it would be acceptable to plant the trees in circular or
oval clumps. He believed that:
There is no man whose taste has been formed on any correct
model, that does not feel and acknowledge the beauty of these
elegant forms, the Oval, the Circle, and the Cone..... and there
are few well-educated persons, who will for a moment compare to
them a multitude of obtuse and acute angles, great and small,
following each other, in fantastical and unmeaning succession.
Sawry Gilpin was horrified by Steuart's remarks and and quoted
all the available authorities in an effort to ridicule them. 'Did
nature ever bound planatations by a circular or oval form?' he
asks, and 'are they to be traced in Claude or Poussin - in Wilson
or in Turner?'. Sawry Gilpin was also able to invoke the names of
his famous uncle, William Gilpin, of
Sir Uvedale Price, who had done so
much to popularise picturesque irregularity, and of Sir Walter
Scott, who had reviewed Steuart's
book in the Quarterly Review. The really maddening thing for
Sawry Gilpin was that Steuart had claimed, in full accord with
Neoplatonism, that the circle and the oval are 'prevalent in all
the most beautiful objects in nature'. 'It appears singular', says
Gilpin, 'that the advocates on each side of the question before us,
should appeal to nature as the foundation of their diametrically
opposite systems'. Gilpin recommended 'the author of the
Planter's Guide to 'spend a day admist the splendid scenery
of the New Forest' in the hope that the experience would convince
him that 'nature' is irregular and not at all like the circles and
ovals of a Neoplatonic dream. We do not know if Steuart took Sawry
Gilpin's advice but the footnote on circles and ovals was dropped
from later editions of the Planter's Guide.
|
|
|
Sawry Gilpin hoped
the 'splendid scenery' of the New Forest would persuade Steuart that
'nature' is fundamentally irregular. His expostulations
provide a clear illustration of how the predominant usage of
'nature' had changed. It had described the circles and squares
which defined the nature of the world and the plan of the Villa Capra. By Gilpin's time it meant the
'shaggy wildness' of areas like the New Forest. |
It can be seen from the controversy between Gilpin and Steuart
that by the nineteenth century the 'nature' which Gilpin, and most
landscape gardeners, believed they should imitate was located near
the bottom of the Neoplatonic hierarchy of forms. 'Nature' had
become the empirical world of everyday experience: not the world of
the forms. The steady advance of empiricism, exerting its inflence
through the axiom that art should imitate nature, became the engine
which drove the aesthetic development of garden and landscape
design in the eighteenth century. The engine faltered after the
turn of the century but flickered back to life towards the end of
the nineteenth century in the work of Robinson and Jekyll. Indeed if abstract art is conceived
as an attempt to analyse the nature of the visible world, as will
be suggested in Chapter 5, then it might be said that a derivative
of the engine is chugging away in the garden to this day.
|